I had a plan
for today’s post, which was to go back through this blog to find where I had
used various news stories to make a point and to revisit those stories asking:
what happened next? As I began to do so, I found that it was a completely
overwhelming task. Over the last three years I have written about under-employment,
corporate tax avoidance, outsourcing, immigration and refugees, global supply
chains, public sector reform, economic insecurity, pensions, corporate
takeovers, air crashes, the NHS, the Greek crisis, the British establishment,
the war in Ukraine, the Chinese economy and many, many other things.
So I have
given up on that idea (for now) and instead will return to just a couple of
things I’ve written about which are in the news again. In my post More on Power (November 2013) I wrote
about the ludicrousness of consumer choice in the electricity ‘market’. Wind
forward to today, and the price comparison sites that would supposedly enable
such a choice are mired in scandal. In my post Pensions (March 2014) I wrote about the deregulation of personal pensions,
a reform supposedly freeing up pensioners to make choices about their pension
pots. Wind forward and we find that already scandals are emerging as pensioners
are ripped-off or conned into making dangerous investments.
The fallacy
that links both these cases (and another current story, that of the need to shop around for the best bank account) is that consumer choice is both
efficient and morally impregnable. It is a logic in which corporations and
consumer rights associations are complicit (see also my post on The Benefits of Work in July 2015). Choice isn’t an unqualified good.
Of course
the neo-liberals are right when they point to the absence of choice as being
one of the failings of State Communism. But that Cold War rhetoric doesn’t take
us very far because the issue isn’t ‘no choice’ versus ‘unlimited choice’:
there are degrees in between. Moreover, as these various examples show, choice
in many markets is fairly meaningless. I sometimes think that market ideologues
genuinely believe that ‘the market’ always and everywhere has the same form as
wandering around fruit and veg stalls, looking at the quality and price of
produce before buying. If so, it’s wholly unrealistic.
The reality
across huge swathes of products – not just energy, pensions or bank accounts
but also mobile phones, insurance or university courses – is nothing like the
Economics 101 textbooks. It’s all but impossible to compare products and
prices, and even if you did so once then within a few days or even minutes
things would change again. Choice in these circumstances is meaningless, and
the constant invocation of choice as a cardinal value is in fact an attempt to
make as central the idea that we are all ‘choosers’. And the significance of
that is not that it is a good thing to be a chooser, but that if choosers make
the wrong choice – as some or many will - then they have only themselves to
blame.
Writ large,
this means that whatever happens to anyone, good or bad, is to their own credit
or reflects their own fault. And so any social situation, no matter how unfair or
wrong it may be, is not just unavoidable but, actually, right. This grotesque
moral spoonerism is the ultimate consequence of the benign or even positive
spin put upon choice.
In political
philosophy, the most sophisticated expression of this valorization of choice as
central is to be found in Robert Nozick’s book Anarchy, State and Utopia (1974). It is a beautifully written and
intellectually elegant book that I would recommend to anyone. At its heart (as
regards choice) is the ‘Wilt Chamberlain example’ (Chamberlain being a famous
basketball player). Nozick argues that if before Chamberlain plays a game
everyone agrees that the distribution of income in society is fair (even, say, if
it is equal); and if, then, everyone who pays to watch Chamberlain play does so
as a free choice; and if, then, as a result Chamberlain has more money than
everyone else; then that new unequal distribution of income must also be fair,
as everyone has chosen it.
There are two
flaws in this argument. One is that it is only Chamberlain and those who paid
to see him who have consented to the new income distribution. What about everyone else? If consent is the key principle for fairness then how can it be fair when they haven't consented? The other is that
if Chamberlain and everyone who paid to see him had known that his extra income
was to be taxed at 100% and redistributed, and he had still chosen to play and
they had still chosen to pay, then the resultant equal income distribution
would also be fair, on the logic of choice.
So choice
doesn’t work, even at the most sophisticated theoretical level, as a guarantor of fairness, and it doesn’t work at the demonstrable
empirical level of how choice actually works in markets. Which doesn’t mean
that it is of no importance if people don’t have
choices. On the contrary, choice is vital for both economic and political
well-being. It’s just that it is not the only thing that matters, or the thing
that matters above all else. It's not a kind of trump card that beats every other aspect of human existence.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: only a member of this blog may post a comment.